X-Message-Number: 15506
From: "Mark Plus" <>
Subject: "Why conservatives dislike scientific progress"
Date: Wed, 31 Jan 2001 10:46:21 -0800

From:

http://reason.com/rb/rb013101.html

Right-wing Technological Dread
Why conservatives dislike scientific progress

By Ronald Bailey, Reason Science Correspondent

A dread of scientific and technological progress is taking hold among 
conservative intellectuals. While not exactly new--right-wingers have often 
cast a cold eye on science and technology--it is becoming more vocal as 
biomedical breathroughs become almost everyday occurences.

Their unease about technology stems from two sources. One is the progressive 
demystification of the world that science has brought about. Life, it turns 
out, is not infused with elan vital but is built up of tiny protein machines 
whose workings are coming to be better and better understood. Similarly, 
evolutionary biology illuminates how all the variegated life on our planet 
has come into existence and sheds light on how the human mind developed and 
how it works.

Such demystification is bad enough, but the second source of conservative 
unease is the fear that technology will fundamentally transform what they 
believe to be "human nature." This conservative alarm over technological 
progress is on display in an elegant essay by Adam Wolfson in the current 
issue of the neoconservative policy quarterly, The Public Interest, where he 
serves as executive editor. In "Politics in a Brave New World," Wolfson 
focuses his concerns on the transformative possibilities of biotechnology 
and genetic engineering.

Wolfson begins by wondering if either liberals or conservatives can muster 
much resistance to technological progress. He first considers reactions by 
liberal thinkers to biotechnological progress, especially to the possibility 
of genetically enhancing human beings. Wolfson applauds the University of 
Maryland's William Galston, a former Clinton domestic policy advisor, for 
his contention that a neo-Kantian understanding of human freedom can "help 
draw the line between technology supportive of our dignity and technology 
that erodes dignity by treating us as means only."

What kind of technology is Galston (and Wolfson) talking about? What would a 
technology that treated us simply as "a means only" be? Electricity, modern 
medicine, televisions, telephones, computers -- are they all not means to 
accomplish our different ends? These technologies certainly shape the way we 
interact with our world, mostly by expanding our choices, but they are 
essentially just better and more efficient means to accomplish our ends. We 
control them; they don t control us.

Wolfson goes on to suggest that because of what he takes to be the inherent 
relativism of their ideology, liberals will likely be unable to meet the 
"challenge of differentiating technologies that fulfill our nature from 
those that destroy it." This is tough language. I wonder what technologies 
to date Wolfson thinks have succeeded in "destroying" our nature? He doesn t 
bother to list any specific ones. New technologies have empowered more and 
more human beings to fulfill their own natures rather than be trapped by 
poverty, disease, and the narrow confines of customary bigotries. But human 
beings do not love less, do not pursue virtue less, nor cherish beauty any 
less because of technological advances.

Wolfson does, however, alert us to a truly pernicious idea that is lurking 
in some quarters of the intellectual left: mandatory government-subsidized 
eugenics in the name of equality. He cites leftist thinker Ronald Dworkin as 
a strong supporter of such a project. This elitist egalitarian impulse, not 
biotechnology, is the real threat. Wolfson realizes this and he does 
properly condemn egalitarianism, but his fear of how egalitarians could 
misuse biotechnology drives him illogically to condemn the technology as 
well. That is somewhat akin to arguing that simply because airplanes can be 
used to bomb cities, we should ban jetliners.

Wolfson turns next to the objections of leading conservatives to scientific 
and technological progress. He commends bioethicist Leon Kass for providing 
the most "powerful and convincing critique of the new eugenics." He cites 
Kass  condemnation of modern science for "its failure to say anything about 
human ends or the good of man." What would this mean? Science is not about 
finding the virtue gene or the compassion gene. Science can and does tell us 
more and more about what our nature is and perhaps how it came to be what it 
is, but science can t tell us what to do with our new knowledge of our 
"given" natures. Understanding ourselves better as embodied and evolved 
beings may well tell us how to achieve our goals more efficiently, but 
science cannot tell us what those goals should be.

Wolfson then considers Friedrich Hayek. He begins by reminding us that Hayek 
warned against "constructive rationalism," the intellectual impulse to 
construct the ideal social order or planned economy. Wolfson suggests that 
technological control over human genetics may be a manifestation of 
"constructive rationalism." He worries about "all this talk of human design, 
rational planning, scientific expertise, and progress and perfection." Here 
Wolfson makes a mistake confusing macro-level with micro-level constructive 
rationalism, if you will. At the micro-level, the activity of biotechnology, 
just like the activities of building a house, a car, or a computer, requires 
rational planning. But it is the rational, voluntary planning of individual 
people contracting with experts to achieve their individual ends. The threat 
to human dignity, liberty, and life arises when elites begin to treat their 
fellow human beings as ends. Their social planning overrides the choices of 
individuals in the name of some other allegedly "higher" goal -- 
egalitarianism, say. As history shows, egalitarians don t need modern 
technology to pursue their leveling agenda.

Wolfson half-heartedly tries to suggest that "biological planning" is 
somehow akin to "social planning." They are not. In the case of biological 
planning or, perhaps more accurately, parental choice, technology empowers 
people to make decisions about their own offspring and how best to help 
their children eventually achieve their own ends. Social planning by 
definition means that the desires of individuals must give way to the goals 
of the group, whether set by a majority or by powerful elites.

But Wolfson will have none of this genetic libertarianism. "The libertarian 
argument that genetic engineering is acceptable so long as it is freely 
chosen by individuals is fraught with difficulties," claims Wolfson. Let s 
take a look at the difficulties that he sees.

"Once genetic engineering is offered on a voluntary basis  social coercion 
at least will come into play," writes Wolfson. His example of social 
coercion today is his assertion that doctors already pressure prospective 
parents to test for genetic abnormalities in developing fetuses. While it's 
true that doctors may pressure, they cannot command--and surely we can all 
agree that doctors should never be given the power to command. In reality, 
most prospective parents are happy to have the opportunity to assure 
themselves that their baby will be healthy.

More broadly speaking, I am puzzled that a conservative is apparently 
against "social coercion," if by that term he means the general standards of 
behavior to which an upstanding member of the community is expected to 
conform, e.g., parents vaccinate their children, they work to support their 
families, they mow their lawns, etc. To some extent, we all already go along 
to get along. That is an expression of our nature as social beings. Wider 
technological choices will not change that.

Another difficulty with genetic engineering that Wolfson foresees is that 
conservatives will have to contend with liberals (egalitarians) who will 
demand government subsidized eugenics for the poor. He s right, but one 
can t justify opposing biotech because egalitarians might try to misuse it. 
By banning biotech, one would, in a sense, be furthering the egalitarian 
project. After all, egalitarians believe that "if we all can t have 
something, then none of us should have it."

For Wolfson "another difficulty is that individuals will not easily exercise 
informed, independent choices when it comes to eugenics. They will almost 
always need the advice of highly trained experts, and as a result their 
 freedom of choice  will be more form than reality."

What an odd argument! Does Wolfson plan to do his own open-heart surgery? 
Repair his own car? Fix his own plumbing? Of course people will need to seek 
out the best advice they can find to guide their decisions about biotech 
medical treatments or genetically enhancing their offspring. And naturally 
some people will be more discriminating and demanding than others about the 
advice and services they receive. But we all rely on experts to get through 
life now and by doing so we are not diminishing our freedom of choice. In 
fact, by having a range of experts on tap, we have substantially expanded 
our choices. Fortunately, too, we can rely on another older technology 
called markets to supply patients and parents with good advice and quality 
services. It works for schooling, grocery stores, restaurants, prescription 
drugs, and there is no reason to think that if we can limit government 
interference with these new technologies, that markets won t work to supply 
us with more rather than fewer choices.

Wolfson also believes that Americans cannot resist the new technologies 
because we live in a society that is pervaded by technological metaphors and 
a protechnology ideology. In Marxist terms, we re like the bourgeoisie who 
cannot see class relations because they are blinkered by their own positions 
in the system. To illustrate how he thinks that technological metaphors have 
taken over and changed our self-conceptions, Wolfson cites a common argument 
brought out by advocates for genetic engineering : Why shouldn t parents be 
allowed to enhance their children s IQs through genetic engineering? After 
all, parents already spend thousands of dollars on education to achieve the 
same goal.

Wolfson counters that this argument confuses achieving a high IQ with the 
larger purposes of education rightly understood. Education was once 
understood, he says, as helping a child "to become a good citizen and a good 
man; it was about the inculcation of virtue. It was about shaping human 
souls, not raising test scores." He s posing a false dichotomy. High test 
scores are not usually thought to be a bar to inculcating virtue or to 
becoming a good citizen. One can be both smart and virtuous.

"A sentiment less generous than education of the young drives the ambition 
to engineer smarter, cleverer beings. It is the desire for an ever more 
complete mastery over nature," complains Wolfson. Again, it is not one or 
the other, it is both. And what s wrong with wanting "more complete mastery 
over nature" anyway? The successful quest for mastery has essentially 
doubled human lifespans in the past century, prevented the starvation of 
hundreds of millions, and lifted millions more out of desperate poverty and 
the darkness of ignorance.

Wolfson rejects as cold-blooded "reductionism" the greater understanding of 
the components of human nature that evolutionary biology and genetics can 
afford us. "The woman who falls for Prince Charming, or the man who courts a 
woman with a voluptuous figure, is said to be really seeking to produce 
attractive, healthy offspring," writes a dismissive Wolfson. He then cites 
James Joyce s sarcastic observation that such a view "tells you that you 
admired the great flanks of Venus because you felt that she would bear you 
burly offspring and admired her great breasts because you felt that she 
would give good milk to her children and yours."

There is no denying that evolutionary psychologists find consistent patterns 
in people s physical criteria for selecting a mate, but does not mean that 
we love our spouses any the less. And whatever genetic and evolutionary 
impulses underlie our appreciation of Venus, she remains as beautiful as 
ever.

At the end of his essay, Wolfson touches on an issue that he believes could 
be very socially and politically disruptive. He fears that the more we learn 
about the genetic differences between people, the more pressure this could 
put on our notions of political equality. Here he is skirting the 
naturalistic fallacy in which "the natural" is mistaken for "the moral 
good." However, political equality is sustained chiefly by the principle 
that people who are responsible moral agents, those who can distinguish 
between right and wrong, deserve equal consideration before the law and a 
respected place in our political community. The broad ability to distinguish 
right from wrong does not depend on the genetics of IQ, skin color, or 
gender. With respect to political equality, genetic differences are 
differences that make no difference.

Wolfson ends by citing Benjamin Franklin s admonition that it is more 
important to be a good parent, a good spouse, a good friend, and a good 
citizen than it is to excel at scientific and technological pursuits. Who 
would argue with that? The pursuit of scientific excellence and 
technological prowess does not controvert those fundamental values.

Ultimately, the conservative worries about technological progress are rooted 
in a deep skepticism about human intentions. And we must surely be vigilant 
against people and ideologies, including conservatism, that might attempt to 
misuse technology to limit human freedom. But the plain fact is that despite 
the horrors of the past century, technology and science have ameliorated far 
more of the ills that afflict humanity than they have exacerbated. In the 
end, the highest expression of our human nature is our ongoing quest to 
understand ever more of the world around us and ourselves.

Ronald Bailey () is Reason Magazine's science 
correspondent.

_________________________________________________________________
Get your FREE download of MSN Explorer at http://explorer.msn.com

Rate This Message: http://www.cryonet.org/cgi-bin/rate.cgi?msg=15506