X-Message-Number: 19199 Date: Tue, 04 Jun 2002 01:15:41 +1000 From: Damien Broderick <> Subject: Re: Constructivism It's not easy to judge this sort of complex intellectual program from sound bites. At the risk of hideous overkill, here's a little something on the topic (I can provide a bibliography offlist should anyone be sufficiently masochistic): ==================== The most remarkable advance in our understanding of the cluster of diverse practices that we call `science' has come about through the realization that scientific work is done by a socially structured community of men and women. The science we consume, so to speak, is the final product of the complex interplay of social forces and material practices. For those whose philosophy of science is but the result of the analysis of printed scientific texts, the illusionist trick of the scientific community in concealing the scaffolding behind a rhetoric of superior rationality has been almost wholly successful. (Harr , 1986:8) It is widely supposed that science is, historically, a new and special way of thinking, quite as startling as upright locomotion in a proto-hominid. Anthropological field studies done in laboratories tend to refute this prejudice. For these observers, usually constructivists, science is not some superior form of cognition happily discovered four centuries ago by Sir Francis Bacon (`we must lead men to the particulars themselves, and their series and order; while men on their side must force themselves for awhile to lay their notions by and begin to familiarise themselves with facts' [cited in Levine, 1987:9, 10]) and now built into the sinew of our divided culture. Rather, on this account, science is a species of story-telling, a kind of narrative (Gilbert and Mulkay, 1984). Science constitutes the myths and rhetorical power-plays of technocracy. As Bruno Latour put it: Now that field studies of laboratory practices are starting to pour in, we are beginning to have a better picture of what scientists do inside the walls of these strange places called `laboratories'. . . . The result, to summarize it in one sentence, was that nothing extraordinary and nothing `scientific' was happening inside the sacred walls of these temples. (Latour, in Knorr-Cetina and Mulkay, 1983: 141) Summarising this renaissance of the sociology of scientific knowledge, Karin Knorr-Cetina discerns a family of analytical positions consonant with that perspective: ethnomethodological or emic studies of scientific practice (Garfinkel, 1967); discourse analysis of scientific discussion and inscription (Gilbert and Mulkay, 1984; Mulkay, 1985); the ethnography of scientific work (Latour and Woolgar, 1979); the relativist program, exemplified by Harry Collins and Trevor Pinch who follow a radical reading of the first edition of Kuhn's The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Collins and Pinch, 1982); and the sociology of knowledge in its `strong' (Barnes, 1977; Bloor, 1976) and `weak' (Chubin and Restivo, in Knorr-Cetina and Mulkay, 1983) forms. What these positions have in common is a thorough-going commitment to a sociological account of scientific activity, founded in careful empirical attention to that practice (whether emic in the extreme - i.e., participatory observation, after the fashion of Collins' and Pinch's studies of alleged paranormal metal-bending, or etic, in the manner of Knorr-Cetina's own studies in the biochemistry, microbiology and technology of plant proteins at Berkeley) and co-ordinated by the twin postulates of `the underdetermination of scientific theories by the evidence; and the thesis of the theory-ladenness of observation' (Knorr-Cetina and Mulkay:3). The impact of the first thesis is to lend dramatic support to a view of scientific knowledge as relative, socially-contingent and subject to (indeed, constituted by) negotiation. Even when Popperian conjecture-and-test models are elaborated into Lakatosian divisions between inviolable hard core and protective belt (so that a shaky theory protects itself from challenge by taking shocks on its ancillary assumptions, diverting them from its central postulates), the rationalist doctrine seems vulnerable to the claim that any theory can outface any evidence, since each theory must perforce be coupled to the adjudicating discourse by innumerable links, the status of which in turn can always be challenged. (But see Lakatos's discussion of this `Duhem-Quine thesis' challenge [ibid.:96-100]: `the well-planned-building of pigeon holes must proceed much faster than the recording of facts which are to be housed in them' [ibid.:100, his italics].) Despite the myth of the crucial experiment which will separate the wheat of truth from the chaff of error, nobody really tosses out a favourite theory purely on the basis of experimental disagreements. Any plausible theory is apparently supported by a host of facts, and apparently undermined by a competing host. As Knorr-Cetina observes, citing Grunbaum: no single theory or theoretical hypothesis can ever be extricated from `the ever present web of collateral assumptions' so as to be open to conclusive refutation. Rather, if certain observational consequences are entailed by a Theory in connection with a set of auxiliary hypotheses and these consequences do not materialize, we can only draw the weaker conclusion that the Theory and the auxiliary assumptions cannot both be true. (ibid.:3) Worse, the second thesis entails that observations are theory-impregnated in the sense that what counts as relevant and proper evidence is partly determined by the theoretical paradigm which the evidence is supposed to test. [Hence, they] cannot serve as independent arbiters in questions of theory choice if their relevance, their descriptive identification and their proper measurement depend on the theories involved. (ibid.:4) Knorr-Cetina is quick to stress that the brand of relativism encouraged by these lines of thought is epistemic rather than judgmental (ibid.:5). While the former asserts merely that knowledge is culture-bound and never strictly `representational' of nature, the second goes much further to claim that any epistemological doctrine is as good as any other. The error in imagining that the second is entailed by the first, she claims, is to presuppose that we know exactly what we mean by the assertion that knowledge is `socially or existentially conditioned'. Yet it is precisely the project of the sociology of scientific knowledge to work out in what sense and to what degree we can speak coherently of knowledge as being rooted in social life. (ibid.:6) The pluralism being urged here is, therefore, pre-eminently methodological. Harry Collins draws the connection nicely: [T]o notice that data has no meaning outside its interpretation requires that interpretations normally given in a matter-of-course, taken for granted, `natural' way are suspended. . . . What we need is radical uncertainty about how things about nature are known. . . . Any alternative view can be crippling to a vigorous exploration of the social construction of the natural world - and indeed to a proper understanding of the role of the natural world in forming our view of it. . . . Though this point can be argued as an epistemological principle the important thing is to adopt it as a methodological imperative (Collins, in Knorr-Cetina, 1983:91) For Collins at least, this does not inevitably lead to a thorough-going ludic deconstructive turn. All theories and experiments might be constructs, built and sustained by discourse traversed by interests, but not all readers have equal access to the texts so constructed. In a provocative and crucial passage, Collins and Pinch observe that the stance of their metal-bending study is `interpretivism'. . . a view which accepts that a participant in a social situation has a privileged understanding when compared with one who is not a participant. [. . .T]o pick on a set of accounts to study - for whatever reason - is to make a judgment about their quality. Otherwise, it would be possible to take any set of visual or aural stimuli as an account of anything. In these circumstances, for example, `The Bluebells of Scotland' played on a comb and paper might well be taken as an account of the mechanisms of, say, oxidative phosphorylation. These would not be very productive circumstances in which to proceed (Collins and Pinch, 1982, Footnote 1:190) This is droll, yet it is also profoundly problematic. What warrant do we accept for dismissing as salient to an understanding of the mechanisms of oxidative phosphorylation the information structurally coded into `The Bluebells of Scotland' played on a comb and paper? Why, that of our collective and established discourse itself, which by hypothesis and empirical evidence is always subject to radical revision and reconstruction. After all, when light is understood to be made of corpuscles, how (prior to quantum theory) might an utterance concerned with waves be expected to bear on our understanding of light? The difference between the two examples is one of degree, since our native competence assures us that talk of waves and talk of particles is at least governed by the same conventions of discourse. Comb-and-paper tunes are interpreted by a wholly different set of codes and contexts from the patterns of information inscribed in scientific discourse. The different semiotic frames generate utterly disjunct schemata or cognitive maps. This need not be the case (we could imagine an oracular culture deriving its truths from comb-and-paper blats!). It is contingently so, however, in our scientific order. And that is a piece of knowledge which can be gained only by participation in the meta-frame, the field of discourse itself. For as the discussion of Crane's and Barnes' accounts made clear, the discourse of science is acquired, like the learning of any language, as much through informal apprenticeship as through any study of specifiable rules: In the sociology of scientific knowledge the researcher will need to develop as far as possible the native competence of the scientific group under study. . . . But, since a crucial characteristic of taken-for-granted rules is that they cannot be fully explicated, an acquaintance with the area through the technical literature will not suffice. The sociologist needs, insofar as it is possible, to acquire the tacit knowledge of the native/scientist members. (ibid.:91-2) This is best done, Collins notes, by participation, a procedure which changes the observer. Hence, any results of such a meta-scientific study will be inaccessible in important ways - not fully available to concretisation - to readers who have not gone through this participatory learning experience. So we find here once more the fundamental problematic of textual reception which in literary studies gives rise to dogmas of Intentional and Affective Fallacies, and, in philosophy, of deconstructive ruptures in any text. Just as one cannot readily unpack a poem using an interpretative technique which is ahistorical, which assumes the `work' to be a jewel-like entity `in itself' (the error of New Criticism), neither can the products of scientific practice be understood directly by reference to `nature'. As Knorr-Cetina and others have stressed, the scientist in the laboratory does not study nature but a material world already drastically shaped and constructed by human intervention: What, after all, is a laboratory? A local accumulation of instruments and devices within a working space composed of chairs and tables. Drawers full of minor utensils, shelves loaded with chemicals and glassware. Refrigerators and freezers stuffed with carefully labelled samples and source-materials: buffer solutions. . . blood samples from the assay rats. . . . All. . . have been specially grown and selectively bred. . . . [W]hether bought or prepared by the scientists themselves, these substances are no less the product of human effort than the measurement devices or the papers on the desk. It would seem, then, that nature is not to be found in the laboratory. . . . (Knorr-Cetina, 1982:3-4) Once this elementary point is taken, it seems self-evident. Surely the key to the scientific enterprise is found in two basic background assumptions. Firstly, that the deep principles of the world within the laboratory can be mapped one-on-one with the world beyond it. Secondly, that this homology is to be investigated through the study of simplified and controlled model cases (sometimes purely mathematical). Yet these assumptions, accepted without scrutiny, act to disguise the constant negotiations involved in constituting the laboratory. What's more, for Knorr-Cetina the activities of scientists are directed pragmatically rather than toward some ideal of `truth': If there is a principle which seems to govern laboratory action, it is the scientists' concern with making things `work', which points to a principle of success rather than one of truth. Needless to say, to make things work - to produce results - is not identical with attempting their falsification. (ibid.:4) Indeed, as she stresses, this pragmatic endeavour is as much directed to attaining recognition of results within the discursive arena of the scientific community. It is hardly `the concern of the laboratory to produce results irrespective of potential criticism' (Idem). The scientists' vocabulary of how things work. . . is in fact a discourse appropriate to the instrumental manufacture of knowledge in the workshop called a `lab'. (Idem.) It is a point expanded upon by Bruno Latour in, for example, his analysis of the rhetorical effects employed by Pasteur in establishing the dominance of his microbiological account of disease (Latour, in Knorr-Cetina, 1983:141-70). First Pasteur takes his laboratory into the field where animals are dying from anthrax. Next he takes the bacillus back to his workplace in the cole Normale Sup rieure, and learns how to grow these tiny new animals (the microbes) and vary their virulence. Finally he reverses his original step and, in a famous experimental demonstration, takes the field into his laboratory, selectively infecting some animals and not others. Now the laboratory becomes coextensive with the world, an achievement (according to Latour's analysis) foreshadowed in, and enabled by, the prior penetration of France by the discursive field of science in the form of the institutions of statistical tabulation: [I]s `all over France' a social construction? Yes indeed; it is a construction made by statistics-gathering institutions. Statistics is a major science in the nineteenth century, as is what `Pasteur', now the label for a larger crowd of Pasteurians, is going to use to watch the spread of the vaccine, and to bring to the still uncertain public a fresh and more grandiosely staged proof of [its] efficacy. . . (ibid.:152) This constantly shifting zone of interpenetration of world and scientific institution is the forum where the realities of science are constructed. The knowable materiality of the world is what, to paraphrase Hilary Putnam, prevents the success of science from being miraculous. Yet the `facts' of that material world are hardly pure and simple. University departments of science do not assiduously scrutinise the `facts' of astrology and parapsychology or mystical cures for cancer, and then find them wanting. These `facts' are simply ignored, because scientists know full well that facts are always constructs, put together by human minds - and these particular `facts', because they have been constructed in the context of ridiculous theories, are too offensive even to trouble debunking. To reiterate: this critical razor cuts both ways. Because the `facts' of science are no less constructed than any other facts, they are equally partial, fallible, doubtful. Theories precede each one of them - we cannot even interpret a photograph without a theory of what to see - and theories follow them, dropping like leaves before the gales of social interests or revolutionary disdain, as the storm of feminism has blasted away the once-rockhard `facts' which `proved' male superiority, and the defeat of institutional racism has obliterated Agassiz's preposterous `facts' about the brain deficits of blacks. So science is, finally, on this account, the kind of story which industrial and postindustrial sophisticates tell about the universe and the creatures which inhabit it, including its storytellers. Its laws are not special laws of `scientific method', sought for so long by anxious philosophers, but the laws of narrative and myth: Science is the totality of the world's legends. The world is the space of their inscription. . . . The domains of myth, science, and literature oscillate frantically back and forth into one another, so that the idea of ever distinguishing between them becomes more and more chimerical. (Harari and Bell, editors' introduction to Serres, 1982:xxi, xxix.) Against this counterintuitive monism, Bruno Latour admits the `naive but nagging question: if nothing scientific is happening in laboratories, why are there laboratories to begin with and why, strangely enough, is the society surrounding them paying for these places where nothing special is produced?' (ibid.:141-2). In many respects it is a naive question, as Latour knows. After all, if nothing metaphysical was happening in medieval monasteries, as atheists surmise, why did society pay for them? If nothing of security is being fostered by the overwhelming multiplication of nuclear weapons and `conventional' arms, why are we all paying so much for them? The answer, as always, lies at the intersection of power and knowledge. Religion and the profession of arms and the exercise of theoretical and laboratory skills are all arenas for the deployment of authority, the insertion of levers, the exertion of force. But surely more can be said? Is there not a difference between science and magic, between crude political bullying and cool technical persuasion? As Latour notes elsewhere: The relativistic position. . . looks ludicrous because of the enormous consequences of science. One cannot equate. . . the careful procedure of corpse interrogation in the Ivory Coast and the careful planning of DNA probes in a California laboratory; the story telling of origin myths somewhere in the South African bush and the Big Bang theory. . . (Latour, 1986:2) Or, to come at it from the rawest, bloodiest bottom-line: is not the special thing about science that, from an equation, it can build a bomb capable of exterminating a city? Can a mantra do as much? This line of argument will not impress everyone. Lakatos cites a story of Popper's concerning a social psychologist, Dr X, who studied physicists interacting in a group. `He observed the "emergence of a leader", the "rallying round effect" in some and the "defence-reaction" in others, the correlation between age, sex, and aggressive behaviour. . . . Popper asked Dr X: "What was the problem the group was discussing?" Dr X was surprised: "Why do you ask? I did not listen to the words. . . ."' (Lakatos, 1978:87). While it would be highly surprising if the group dynamics of scientists failed to echo those of other human groups, surely what is singular about scientific discourse is its unprecedented power of capturing and manipulating non-obvious aspects of the brute or non-intentional world. Interestingly, Lakatos simply cites this tale without comment, evidently regarding it as a knock-down self-refutation of a sociological methodology that, after his death, has become increasingly popular. Latour does find one invariant factor which characterises the activity of modern science (and links it to others): its chosen practice of inscription. A lab, he found, was a place of diverse instruments, some of which `filled large rooms, employed many technicians and took many weeks to run. But their end result, no matter the field, was always a small window through which one could read a very few signs from a rather poor repertoire (diagrams, blots, bands, columns). . . . When these resources were lacking, the selfsame scientists stuttered, hesitated, and talked nonsense. . .' (Latour, 1986:3). Leave them their `rational' minds, their access to scientific `paradigms' and `methods' - without those specified ways of writing and diagramming, without the story-telling tools of science, scientists fall away into a curious tongue-tied loss of power. This power which scientific modes of cognition provide is notable, Latour claims, for the unique advantage they give in the rhetorical or polemical situation. `You doubt of what I say? I'll show you.' And, without moving more than a few inches, I unfold in front of your eyes figures, diagrams. . . present things that are far away and with which some sort of two-way connection has now been established. I do not think the importance of this simple mechanism can be overestimated. (ibid.:14) It is not altogether clear to me that this segregates scientific from alchemical or astrological iconographies unless we adduce post facto the results of their manipulations (which in turn a Feyerabendian relativist would surely see as unconvincing: don't poisoned Zanade chickens accurately forecast the future?). Latour skirts this issue: The manipulation of substances in gallipots and alembics becomes chemistry only when all the substances can be written in a homogeneous language where everything is simultaneously presented to the eye. The writing of words inside a classification are not enough. Chemistry becomes powerful only when a visual vocabulary is invented that replaces the manipulations by calculations of formulas. (Idem) The end result of such formal reduction in chemistry is, of course, Mendeleiev's table of the elements, and thence the quantum theory which, according to the current canonical reading, underlies it. Such ultimate inscriptions do not merely condense untold masses of empirical data and their correlations; they permit algorithmic extrapolations of the formulae which (to some limited extent at least) can be mapped onto experiential results. Hence, turning the tables, Wolpert can state that The quantitative aspect of science is fundamental. . . . One cannot imagine a science of motion, a successful science, that does not rely on the calculus. If the relativists wish to persuade us of social constructs, they will have to provide, at the least, major counter-examples. (Wolpert, 1992:121) I find this objection persuasive. However socially constructed Newton's theory of gravitation was, it would scarcely have had great success if (influenced, let us say, by the Holy Trinity) it had proposed an inverse cube law. Oddly enough, though, in an interesting thought-experiment John Barrow has recently imagined a kind of empirical computerised mathematics that an extraterrestrial culture might employ, extremely inelegant by Earthly standards but perhaps no less powerful (Barrow, 1992:178-81). Analogously, perhaps, La Perouse's map-making for Louis XVI exemplifies the power of inscribed visualisation, offering a parable which makes it plain that political context can be of prime importance: Commercial interests, capitalist spirit, imperialism, thirst for knowledge, are empty terms as long as one does not take into account Mercator's projection, marine clocks [etc. . .]. But, on the other hand, no innovation in the way longitude and latitudes are calculated, clocks are built [etc], would make any difference whatsoever if they did not help to muster, align, and win over new and unexpected allies, far away, in Versailles. (Latour, 1986:6) In short, these effects are the results of what ecologist Richard Levins and evolutionist Richard Lewontin term active `dialectical' co-determination: interaction of the divers explanatory elements (Levins and Lewontin, 1985). Latour stresses this over-determination: To maintain only the second line of argument would offer a mystical view of the powers provided by semiotic material - as did Derrida [in Of Grammatology]; to maintain only the first would be to offer an idealist explanation (even if clad in materialist clothes). (Idem) So, too, argue the discourse theorists of the sociology of scientific knowledge, for the cognitive tools of contemporary science. These have their puissant effect within specific and circumscribed social contexts: first, the forums of scientific construction and reception; secondly, within the economic and ideological fields which themselves function to constitute those tools and that practice (Charlesworth, Farrall, Stokes, Turnbull, 1989). There have been a number of attempts to pursue such arguments directly in literary theoretic terms (as, fleetingly, Latour has done in that killing swipe at Derrida's deconstructive hubris; see also Rorty, 1989). It is possible simply to read the published texts of science with an eye to the rhetorical machinery they employ, and to scrutinise the canonical texts of literature for the discourses of science which somewhat surprisingly imbricate their own specialised narrative codes (Beer, 1983; Levine, 1988). One may go further, as the emerging discipline of `Science and Literature studies' is doing, and build, as George Levine recommends, from certain fundamentally monist assumptions: first, that science and literature are two alternative but related expressions of a culture's values, assumptions, and intellectual frameworks; second, that understanding science in its relation to culture and literature requires some understanding not only of its own internal processes, but of the pressures upon it exercised by social, political, aesthetic, psychological, and biographical forces; third, that the idea of `influence' of one upon the other must work both ways. . . (Levine, 1987:vii) Finally, one might attempt to discern general invariant patterns underlying the structures of these evidently different enterprises (Jakobson, in Waugh, 1985:3) - not with a view to sinking both broad classes of discursive regimes into an uninterestingly blurred identity, but in the hope of discerning the diffentiae specifica in the way each deploys common procedures of construing and constructing the world and its texts, of coding and decoding this information, and of rendering such abstract information flows, via social, historical and other contexts and frames, into human meanings. The traditional name for this textual activity is rhetoric. (THE ARCHITECTURE OF BABEL: Discourses of Literature and Science) Rate This Message: http://www.cryonet.org/cgi-bin/rate.cgi?msg=19199