X-Message-Number: 23395 From: Date: Fri, 6 Feb 2004 20:50:49 EST Subject: Beware the Butler These notes are more or less random snippets from YOUNIVERSE, or related to topics therein. The order in the book is different, and the treatment often different and usually longer. Beware the Butler There is no agreement on the proper range of philosophy, or the proper distinction between philosophy and science. A reasonable view might be that philosophy is mainly concerned with language, its use to reveal or conceal. There is no agreement on the meaning of meaning, or the proper definition of a proposition. Here's a little example involving the slippery concept of "proposition" and the depth of language. Consider the sentence, "There is dust on this table." Is it a proposition? (This sentence, or a similar one, is used by R.M. Hare in Sorting Out Ethics, Oxford 1997.) At first thought, it is a prime instance of a genuine proposition, a statement of fact which is either true or false. One might quibble about quantitative questions, how much dust it takes to entitle a surface to be called dusty, or how big a grain qualifies as a dust grain, but most of us would disregard that. However, we have not inquired about the context of the sentence. Suppose it was spoken in a stern tone of voice by a butler to a maid. It might then be surmised that the real message was: "Look at this, you lazy slut, I am distinctly annoyed, and you had better shape up pronto." All right, an English butler probably wouldn't say "shape up pronto," but there are probably a few butlers in Texas too. In any case, identical sentences (the same exact string of symbols, written/read at different times or places) can have different meanings. If you let your guard down just a little you may be sucker-punched. At least, that is one way to read the Butler lesson, but I don't entirely agree. We must avoid confusing meaning with consequences or reactions. I would say the sentence about dust on the table means just what it says, and nothing more, regardless of who is listening or how the listener reacts or interprets what she hears, or even what the speaker intends. After all, the speaker or writer does not necessarily know how to convey what he intends, or may be deliberately deceptive; and the listener or reader can misperceive or be misled. We are therefore led into a murky need to rely on "reasonable" writers and readers, so it boils down to an uneasy reliance on collective experience and judgment. As a side light, philosophers, like most specialists, are prone to inventing jargon, sometimes without need. To distinguish different types of sentences, J. L. Austin (How to Do Things with Words, Oxford, 1962) names three types of talk--locution, illocution, and perlocution. His main point is that a perlocutionary act is one intended to produce a consequence, not necessarily the apparent one. For example, if a mean adult wants a sullen child to misbehave, the adult might tell the child very sternly to behave, expecting defiance which would then be punished. So the same words might seem to have very different meanings as illocutions or perclutions--but my comment is the same as in the paragraph above. Indeed, the prevalence of jargon in many works of professional philosophers gets so out of hand that the work is inaccessible to the layman--which is often the layman's good luck, to be sure. Another change in the Update section on the Youniverse site, www.younivese.net Robert Ettinger Content-Type: text/html; charset="US-ASCII" [ AUTOMATICALLY SKIPPING HTML ENCODING! ] Rate This Message: http://www.cryonet.org/cgi-bin/rate.cgi?msg=23395