X-Message-Number: 3927 From: (David Stodolsky) Subject: Locating the Mind Date: Tue, 28 Feb 95 19:10:19 +0100 (CET) There has been repeated discussion about how certain individuals refuse to consider suspension because of "irrational" social reasons. One example discussed recently is very wealthy persons who could easily be suspended, but do not do so because they would probably be just ordinary persons in the future. Perhaps a more correct analysis is that the social framework within which they have been successful might not even exist in the future. For example, what would be the meaning of great physical wealth in the future when nanomachines could generate physical objects on command? Another case is the person who refuses to consider suspension, because their family or friends would not be present when they are resuscitated. These concerns may not be irrational. One implication of this article on sociality is that the mind's natural environment is a series of organizational structures. The social environments mentioned above and others may be necessary for the survival of the mind as a functional unit. This may sound far fetched, but consider the ant or termite alone, outside of its social unit, which many consider a single organism. What would be its chance of survival or even being able to function effectively in its traditional environment? While humans are not "hard wired" in the same way as these simple organisms, the learning process may program us into similar patterns of interdependence. In this case, the mind is located at the intersection of multiple organizational units, without which it loses much of its ability to function or even to exist in the traditional sense. There have been proposals that the mind is diffuse and not totally dependent on the preservation of brain structure. Perhaps this article offers a way to integrate these "far out" views into a more comprehensive picture of individual survival. In any case, the suggestion here is that biological preservation alone, no matter how perfect, may not be enough to avoid the destruction of the mind and one's identity. dss ---- psycoloquy.95.6.01.group-selection.1.caporael Monday 20 February 1995 ISSN 1055-0143 (51 pars, 1 table, 1 note, 44 refs, 999 lines) PSYCOLOQUY is sponsored by the American Psychological Association (APA) Copyright 1995 Linnda R. Caporael SOCIALITY: COORDINATING BODIES, MINDS AND GROUPS Linnda R. Caporael Department of Science and Technology Studies Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute Troy, NY 12180 ABSTRACT: Human interaction, as opposed to aggregation, occurs in face-to-face groups. "Sociality theory" proposes that such groups have a nested, hierarchical structure, consisting of a few basic variations, or "core configurations." These function in the coordination of human behavior, and are repeatedly assembled, generation to generation, in human ontogeny, and in daily life. If face-to-face groups are "the mind's natural environment," then we should expect human mental systems to correlate with core configurations. Features of groups that recur across generations could provide a descriptive paradigm for testable and non-intuitive evolutionary hypotheses about social and cognitive processes. This target article sketches three major topics in sociality theory, roughly corresponding to the interests of biologists, psychologists, and social scientists. These are (1) a multiple levels-of-selection view of Darwinism, part group selectionism, part developmental systems theory; (2) structural and psychological features of repeatedly assembled, concretely situated face-to-face coordination; and (3) superordinate, "unsituated" coordination at the level of large-scale societies. Sociality theory predicts a tension, perhaps unresolvable, between the social construction of knowledge, which facilitates coordination within groups, and the negotiation of the habitat, which requires some correspondence with contingencies in specific situations. This tension is relevant to ongoing debates about scientific realism, constructivism, and relativism in the philosophy and sociology of knowledge. KEYWORDS: developmental systems theory, group coordination, group selection, hierarchy, human evolution, social cognition, social identity, teleofunctionalism I. INTRODUCTION 1. Most behavioral and social sciences assume human sociality is a by-product of individualism. Briefly put, individuals are fundamentally self-interested; "social" refers to the exchange of costs and benefits in the pursuit of outcomes of purely personal value, and "society" is the aggregate of individuals in pursuit of their respective self-interests. To this view of "economic man," which long pre-dated Darwin, sociobiology added the idea that individual advantage could be measured in the currency of genes. In theories stressing the importance of group living, conspecifics are viewed largely as a class of objects, more unpredictable than others, but requiring substantial intelligence on the part of the actor to use these "social objects" to achieve genetic ends through alliances, manipulation, or exploitation (Byrne & Whiten, 1988). In contrast, by "social," I refer to a structural continuum of obligate interdependence, without which individual prospects for reproduction and survival to reproductive age are reduced. 2. Humans are obligately interdependent, not only for acquiring their daily bread, but also for the daily operation of their minds. When Adam Smith proposed the "invisible hand" of self-interest, he took for granted that the butcher, the brewer, the baker -- and their families who worked in the business -- were organized in workshops, which were in guilds, which were in villages, which were in districts, which had seasonal fairs and religious celebrations. In the 18th century, the skills for butchering, brewing, and baking were accumulated through generations, passed from adult to child, and repeated in daily, weekly and seasonal cycles of activity. Butchering, brewing and baking demanded finely tuned sensory and motor coordination; familiarity with variable materials, tools and methods; a marketplace, of course; and coordination among these physical, mental and social components. Today, telecommunications and transportation technologies expose the significance of this coordination. People still organize themselves in groups, but some of these no longer need to be face-to-face groups, constrained by space and time in a nested hierarchy of guild, village, district, etc. 3. Hull (1988) described a nested hierarchical organization in science similar to the one in village life; a "demic structure" composed of small research groups, "conceptual demes," and seasonal society meetings. This description accords very well with psychological research on the nested, hierarchical structure of social identity (Turner, 1987). I propose that the demic structure of science described by Hull is more general, and it is paralleled by a "demic structure" of mind.AE1AA The parallelism suggests that the "mind's natural environment" can be more adequately specified in terms of functional organizational structure than it can be by invoking inclusive fitness theory and "life in the Pleistocene" (Tooby & Cosmides, 1992). Given a descriptive paradigm of the human evolutionary environment, it should be possible to derive testable, nonobvious hypotheses about human mental systems. 4. Before we can consider the "invisible hand" of demic structure, however, we need an evolutionary framework that relieves us of the individualistic assumptions built into the gene-centered view. The traditional single-level, gene-centered evolutionary analysis, based on genetic self-sacrifice, inclusive fitness, or number of offspring, does not lend itself to discussions of hierarchical organization for social structure or mental systems. ===================================== David S. Stodolsky, PhD * Social * Internet: Tornskadestien 2, st. th. * Research * Tel.: + 45 38 33 03 30 DK-2400 Copenhagen NV, Denmark * Methods * Fax: + 45 38 33 88 80 Rate This Message: http://www.cryonet.org/cgi-bin/rate.cgi?msg=3927