X-Message-Number: 8029 Date: 09 Apr 97 22:54:27 EDT From: "Steven B. Harris" <> Subject: Surprise and the Subconscious Dear Cryonet: Mike Perry writes: >>One way to resolve the apparent inconsistency is to think about what "agent" is involved. Suppose, as a thought experiment, that the brain of a person (not necessarily human, but a consci- ous being) is divided into regions A and B that correspond to different entities or "agents." This person communicates in English, and generally behaves and functions enough like a human that its consciousness can be tested in much the same way--plus we have advanced technology as needed. It is found that (1) region A is always active when the person is conscious, (2) when A is inactive the person is never conscious, and (3) A is the smallest possible region of the brain with these properties. So A, to all appearances, is the "seat of consciousness." By analysis, though, it is found that B is very much like A, except that B *only* communicates with A. When A is inactive, B may be active, but it has no "hookup" with the outside world and its activity is not normally apparent. In effect B is a fully conscious entity in its own right, but it is not the "person" that is represented in A. A uses B as a "slave"--with no direct awareness of any "feelings" B may have. I'm no expert on the human brain, but it seems possible it could have regions like B. I've heard of certain creative people who can "work" on problems when they are not consciously aware of what they are doing, and they find answers. Perhaps they have "B-regions" that are actually conscious, to some degree, but it isn't "their" consciousness. Following this train of thought, we might imagine that much or all of the body's CNS is capable of consciousness to some extent, yet it isn't the "seat of consciousness" to the person who inhabits that body. << ------------------------------------------------------------- Comment: As Freud and Jung have pointed out, dream analysis indicates that something like the above must be so. When a person dreams, they move through a world which is an imaginary movie set, populated with "other people" who are also wholly imaginary. But who, then, is doing the imagining? Not the "dreamer," it seems, for the dreamer is frequently surprised (to some extent-- more on this later) by things that happen in dreams. Obviously during a dream, the mind is "split" into at least two parts. One part is "doing" the simulation of reality (like your own personal holodeck computer), and the other part is doing the experiencing of that reality. Thus for Freud the mind comes in at least two parts-- a conscious, and a subconscious that does imaginary simulations (a "part B"). The part B gets input from the environment, but it doesn't need to. Its output is (at the very least) nonverbal. It is not clear whether the subconscious is "conscious" in the usual Turing sense of being another functioning person (again, consider the analogy of the holodeck computer-- it doesn't HAVE to be). But there is indirect evidence that the subconscious is "conscious," albeit not very verbal, in much the same way that there is evidence that nonverbal animals are consciousness. During waking, the output of the subconscious is somewhat suppressed by environmental stimuli, but there is no reason to imagine that it is inactive. So what is the subconscious doing, during waking? Some speculation follows. First of all, much experience indicates that the brain possesses complex information-processing routines which are not directly accessible to the conscious. Simple examples are the systems that controls physiologic balance (e.g., breathing), and the higher-level systems that run motor behavior. Some of these are complex. Indeed, most people have had the experience of having their own bodies "drive them to work," or begin to, when they didn't intend to go there, but had instead started out from home without paying sufficient attention. Of course, it is not the body that drives one to work automatically in such cases, but an automatic subprogram or subroutine (mental "agent," if you will) that incorporates a lot of high-level tasks (visual recognition, fine motor control, decision making at traffic lights, etc, etc). In other words, something *quite* sophisticated (so sophisticated that it is only now just becoming a realistic goal with today's computer systems). There is also evidence for subconscious information-processing of a more purely cerebral nature. It is possible (for example) to show that information presented to the brain through the ears while attention has been diverted, and which is not accessible to the consciousness, nevertheless affects decision-making. One can, for instance, present the brain with two simultaneous conversations, only one of which can be "listened to," by the conscious mind, at a time-- and only one of which is available on formal testing. But the information content of both conversations can be shown to be available on indirect testing. One must conclude from these tests that either the subject is lying when he states that he doesn't know fact A which was presented in a conversation he wasn't paying attention to (but which can be shown to be influencing a test choice when he is forced to "guess"), or else one must conclude that he actually doesn't "know" the fact, but that "somebody else" DOES (i.e., his subconscious mind, which doesn't do the speaking). Physically, where is the center of such "para-conscious" information-processing? In some experiments people are presented patterns of symbols associated with an event (a good or bad weather situation, for instance), and then forced, on the basis of more symbols, to guess about a "forecast." In these experim- ents the information is shown to be processed partly in the basal ganglia. Normal people soon develop "intuitive" feelings about what patterns of symbols predict, long before they can articulate the relationships, whereas people with basal ganglia damage (Parkinson's disease patients) cannot do this. So some of the brain's "para-conscious" inductive pattern recognition is done at the same physical level that controls higher level motor tasks like driving (perhaps not surprisingly). If anything, evidence points to our basal ganglia (including the thalami) being the seat of our intuitive "subconscious" minds (when it comes to pattern recognition), but NOT our articulate, logical, conscious minds (Although this too is simplistic, as diseases of the basal ganglia like Huntington's disease cause severe dementia). At the same time, a well-known series of experiments suggests that the right brain processes information independently of the left brain, and presents this information to the left brain somewhat inarticulately, in the form of emotional responses, and also (perhaps) in more direct stimuli to act. It is probable, then, that some of the "subconscious" is located in the right-brain (perhaps in the right cortex, in somewhat the same way that speech seems localized in the left cortex in most people). What does the subconscious (which we've here referred to as one entity, but which may of course be composed of many Minksi-an "agents") ordinarily do, during waking? Some of this has already been alluded to. Apparently the subconscious processes informa- tion at many levels from the surroundings, and abstracts physical patterns, emotional signals, and physical threats quite independently of "conscious" (by which I mean articulatable) thought. Its conclusions are then presented to the consciousness in various ways, ranging from presenting (or hitting!) the conscious mind with emotions (fear, anxiety, happiness, lust, etc, etc), to causing in it an odd intuitive "preference" for certain actions, which is hard for the consciousness to rationa- lly explain (hence the origin of irrational ESP and "spiritual knowledge" myths). It may even be that the subconscious (in the form of one or more agents) has some direct control over motor actions, and more directly influences physical behavior. If this happens, then here also the process may be difficult for the "speaking consciousness" to explain (to put it mildly). For example, when a "murderer" says "I didn't mean to kill him-- the gun just went off," he may be speaking the literal truth about how the situation appeared to the "mental agent" that is (or "who" is) doing the talking. Thus, a person judicially put to death while protesting his innocence of a murder can be viewed (somewhat macabrely) as a collection of mental agents, only some of which are "guilty," and in many cases perhaps not including the mental agent who is vocalizing innocence. Understanding this possibility is not very comforting, to be sure-- but then understanding rarely is. The monolithic view of consciousness which prevailed before Freud, did so partly because this view is somewhat "explicable" (if such "explanations" count as explanations) in terms of religious models. In these models, those complex ideas and behavioral proddings which arose in the conscious mind independently of consciousness, were explained as the influence of devils or the spirit of the divine. It took an atheistic worldview to do better. Development of a multi-agent view of consciousness has also in the past been badly hampered by the fact that the mind seems to be equipped with a prevarication or self-justification module (or Munchausen Circuit, if you will) which causes the "speaking consciousness" to quite often fabricate reasons for behavior. Some of these can be downright silly. Experimenters in the early commissurotomy right-brain/left-brain experiments, for instance, were quite often shocked by the fact that the left brain had a propensity to "explain" things that the right-brain/left hand did, even when it was absolutely clear to the experimenters that the explanation was bogus (due to the fact that the left brain did not have the knowledge which caused the left hand to do what it was doing). So why did the left brain feel the need to "explain" actions that it had no control over? We still don't know, but the horror is that such behavior **is not limited to split-brain models.** More recently, investigators have been amazed to find that in normal intact persons the conscious mind quite often gives completely bogus explanations for behaviors which are the result of unconsciously processed information, and that this lying behavior doesn't stop until the right brain is anesthetized by an injection of barbiturate into the right carotid. Only then do people become honest, saying that they don't know why they chose a certain test answer. If this is the way our minds are set up, it is a wonder that human beings have made any cultural or scientific progress at all. What a terrible handicap to honest communication! (It's enough to make one cynical). One can only speculate about the social evolutionary pressures which must have driven development of such a formal spoken "modesty protector" for unconscious drives, and for unconscious information-processing in general. Is there anything else we can say about how the subconscious processes information? How the subconscious works to process social information is again suggested by the content of dreams. In dreams, an entire "stage-show" is set up by one part of the mind (or by a submind, is you like), and in it, characters are allowed to talk and interact, as in life. Dreams allow access of the speaking consciousness to this stage show, but the most interesting question is what happens to all of this when the sleeper wakes. Does the stage show disappear-- its only purpose having been to entertain "us" when "we" are asleep? This seems unlikely. A better explanation is that the "stage show" of dreams actually runs all the time, but that in waking it is entrained by inputs from the real world (which largely displace it in consciousness), so that the characters and social models are continuously updated and allowed to run as simulations in a less free way than in dreams (when allowed to diverge, such simulations are known as "daydreams"). How do we, as social beings, know how another person is likely to react, if we say X as opposed to Y? Possibly the same way we know that a soccer-b- all is going to go HERE rather than THERE if we hit it THIS way rather than THAT way. In all these cases, simulations have been set up and run, largely but not completely beneath the level of consciousness, and the results made available to us without any of the messy calculatory details. When the novelist jokes that he needed to write another novel in a series in order to "find out" what happened to the characters/people he cared about, such a statement should be seen as only half specious. Most, if not all, novelists have had the feeling that characters initially created have sometimes taken on a life of their own, balkily refusing to say or do what the author had initially intended. From whence does such a decidedly odd (but almost universal) feeling come? Answer: it is entirely explainable in terms of unconscious social modeling, something into which every successful story-writer must tap. And also every successful politician, and indeed every socially successful person. Recently, much has been written about "E.Q." or emotional I.Q.-- that mental ability which allows a person to successfully model another person's internal state and behavior. People with low E.Q.s can be quite intelligent in many formal ways but they are severely handicapped in social situations. (Examples are the nearly autistic physicist P.A.M. Dirac and chemist Irving Langmuir, model for the socially retarded scientist in Vonnegut's _Cat's Cradle_.) Similarly handicapped are many schizophrenics, who often suffer the same devastating failure to be able to internally model other people's feelings and behaviors (as well as other mental handicaps). The question of why humans have developed social cloaks for their subconscious activities may be difficult, but the question of why humans possess these activities in the first place is not. People without them have terrible problems interacting with others. Are the one or more "agents" which make up the unconscious mind, themselves "conscious"? To this, it must be answered that it (or they) have all the elements of consciousness, save speech. The subconscious is capable of interpreting spoken language, and modeling complex social interactions. To use a recent metaphor from cryonet, it certainly "cringes" appropriately, and in shaded and appropriate response to far more complex stimuli than would a dog or even a chimp. Thus, the subconscious is certainly conscious in the ordinary sense, albeit mute. --- Before winding up, I'd like to put in a few words about solipsism. For nearly the entire history of philosophy there has been an undecidable running debate between objective realists and idealists. The objective realists hold that there exists an objective external world outside consciousness, which "explains" the phenomena of which consciousness becomes aware. The idealists, on the other hand, point out that all phenomena which we know anything of are (by definition) mental events, and thus an objective world is in principle completely unknowable of itself, and therefore the existence of objective reality is a hypothesis which doesn't add anything to the question of why events happen. Solipsists are egoistic persons who have taken idealism to its logical conclusion, and decided that reality is nothing more than their own mental reality, with nothing more than this existing. Solipsism is impossible to disprove, and the only thing one can say about it, is that for all of that, it's hard for the average person to keep pure. The philosopher Bertrand Russell was once entertained by a letter from a solipsist, who wrote that, since solipsism was impossible to disprove, why then didn't more people believe in solipsism as a philosophy? Russell wrote back in his incomparably ironic style, asking the correspondent why he couldn't make himself *believe* that more people didn't believe in solipsism.... As Russell's comments suggest, one difficulty with solipsism is the emotion of surprise. Surprise results (as it did for Russell's correspondent) when one's observations or sensations don't correspond with what one expected, on the basis of one's model of "reality." Surprise is thus a fundamental emotion, and perhaps a more important one than it is usually given credit for being. For the objective realist, surprise (which always results from inductive mal-prediction) is the fundamental weeder-out of bad inductive theories about the objective universe (c.f. Popper's theories of science). For the idealist, surprise is the ultimate challenge to explain. How does one account for stimuli one is not expecting? The solipsist, when confronted with surprise, is forced into simple denial: the solipsist must either deny the existence of surprise (clever tack), or else must simply hold somewhat contrarily that it implies no contradiction in terms for one to surprise one's self. For the non-solipsist, however, the essence of consciousness is knowledge, and the element of surprise in unexpected stimuli to a conscious being is prima fasciae evidence of the existence of *something* about which there has been a demonstrated lack of predictive knowledge-- and thus, something "outside" (by definition) that consciousness. If solipsists write letters to philosophers asking for explanations, shouldn't they already know what to expect by way of answers? To Rene Descartes' famous maxim (the so-called Cogito): "I think, therefore I am," the non-solipsist will add a corollary: "Furthermore, I'm often surprised, therefore there is more to existence than just me." The solipsist will, of course, at this point object that the corollary is unfairly tautological, since identity has been implicitly defined (arbitrarily) in terms of knowledge, and this used to "deduce" existence of something other than a single identity, from the fact of that identity's lack of predictive knowledge. But this is an unfair criticism, inasmuch as all statements which are "logically true" or deductively true (things that Kant would say we know by "pure reason") are necessarily tautologies. Descartes' _Cogito_ is itself a tautology (at best, an "enthymeme," with a hidden premise), if one looks closely. If the reader is still with me at this point, and hasn't gone to sleep, it is possible to analyze some of the previous philosophical debate on Cryonet in terms of what the emotion of surprise means to the average person. At the beginning of this letter, I made the explicit argument that the existence of surprise in a dream argued for the existence of more than one "model-producing" conscious entity in the brain of a dreaming person. At the same time, I can also as long time experimental dreamer report that dreams are not as surprising as real-life events. In dreams, "objects" sometimes do surprising things, but "people" only rarely do, and "people" never seen to act in _totally_ inexplicable ways (as they do occasionally in real life-- especially women <g>). In dreams, I have noted that characters act in ways that are understandable and somewhat stereotyped, almost as people in a bad novel (perhaps this says something about this author's creativity...). Moreover, I have noted that more than once, characters in my dreams seen to share a shocking amount of my own knowledge about the world, so much so that I've frequently awakened wishing that I might somewhere find a real person who was as much an alter-ego as someone I had met in a dream (no doubt if I actually did, I would be spectacularly bored in a short time, of course). It's no coincidence that the characters in my dreams share my knowledge, for we are dipping at the same well, so to speak. My dream characters thus share some of my identity, but not quite all of it. Empirically, one of the primary things that convinces me of the separate reality/identity of other people, and of the non-dream nature of the "waking world," is that in my waking hours other people ("real people") do things which are utterly unexpected. I believe that (except for die-hard solipsists) we accord identity to other people partly on this basis. If other people acted precisely as we expected them to, we would soon no doubt come to see them as nothing more than complicated devices, not deserving of the same status and regard with which we hold ourselves. A machine which began to slavishly act in predictable ways in a conversation would not pass the Turing test-- indeed, this is the most damning of machine-like behaviors in such a test. Moreover, I propose that one reason Searle's "Chinese Room" seems to be intrinsically incapable of consciousness to some imaginers, is that the Chinese Room is intrinsically and by definition incapable of surprising us. You can, after all, look up and predict anything it does, in a big book of rules. For that reason, it doesn't pass the Descartes Corollary test (the "Surprise Test"), and neither do any computers which run with discrete and predictable binary programs. Here, I don't mean "predictable" in terms of the Turing halting problem, I mean predicable from the view of repeatability of behavior. Humans would have exactly the same consciousness problem, if they were found to be this kind of machine. What would happen if we were to make a matter duplicator which turned out copies of people who always did exactly the same thing, perhaps for hours or days on end, after they stepped off the replicator pad, and into the test-room? We might well begin to regard humans in a different light, in that case. Suppose I feel "conscious," and yet am doing only exactly what I am expected and predicted to do, just like an unconscious robot-- is that not a paradox? (Perhaps only a paradox of the sorites type?) Is such a duplicator and test-room even possible, then? Some people, after due consideration, would say no-- that different conditions of the room at different times would preclude duplicate responses of the replicated human. But what if you replicate the room also? Now many people will take refuge in quantum mechanics, and argue that any such test-room will be embedded in the universe, and will begin to diverge from any duplicate (even a perfect one) which appears at another time and place. We've seen this argument on Cryonet. Another way to frame such an argument is to say that many people refuse to accept the consciousness of any being found to be operating according to fixed and completely deterministic rules, and thus incapable of doing something we don't expect from looking at a prior simulation. If a being can't, in principle, provide a surprise for one who knows enough about it, some people begin to get solipsistic about its "consciousness." Not to do so would be to admit to the possibility of a certain determinism of action for "conscious beings," which bothers many people. As to whether it should or not, I cannot say.* Steve Harris * "Arguments" about determinism have some of the same odd character as arguments about solipsism. If someone argues for determinism, the rejoinder is: "What makes you say that..?" If the argument is for some element of randomness, the rejoinder is: "Oh, you're just saying that..." People who want to argue a third alternative need to be reminded, as Minski does, that there isn't one. Rate This Message: http://www.cryonet.org/cgi-bin/rate.cgi?msg=8029